Tuesday, April 16, 2019
Hume and Kant on Free
Hume and Kant on Free pull up stakes EssayAbstr get alongThis paper is an attempt to show how Kants ideas concerning realistic and transcendental riddom of the pull up stakes was a signifi nookiet correction to the parallel theories of Hume. It starts out by clarifying Humes critique of handsome will, especially as it appears in An examination Concerning Human Understanding. It draws the conclusion that Humes philosophy is espousing suspense, and that Kants feat is to overcome this unbelief and relaxation methodore trust in curtilage. The philosophy of Kant is outlined in come out to profess the last point. It is generally agreed that Kant supplied the definitive stamp to philosophy that ushered in the modern age. Hume, though hugely influential in his time, and a favorite in the French salons of philosophy, fell into disrepute in the twee era, and exclusively since has fix a root of restored interest. Yet Hume is the philosopher cited by Kant as having stirred h im from his dogmatic slumbers. He had espoused a philosophy of empirical hesitation, so thorough and devastating in its scope that it became impotential for Kant to keep in his settled certainties of Newtonian lore. It was the spur that carried him on to compose the brushup of Pure Reason (1781), where reason is restored, and man is once more vindicated as a rational being.Just because he refuted and answered Humes skepticism does non imply that the latter philosophy is nullified. We must keep this in master object, that Humes skepticism is completely valid as far as sense experience is concerned, and Kant does non refute any part of this philosophy. What he does is posit a further dimension to gracious taste, specifi call backy, the synthetic a priori readiness of the mind, the existence of which Hume did non suspect. Only after this addition is the primacy of reason restored. So we cannot say that Kant has destroyed Humes philosophy, rather he has added to it.Central t o Humes skepticism is his critique of cause and effect, which is spelled out to its close profound depths in chapter VII of the An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748). The preliminary task is to outline the likeness belief. The premise to this is that all copeledge begins from sense experience. Among such we atomic number 18 able to distinguish between primary election and supportary sensations. The primary sensations argon extension, motion, inertia etc, which are and so the concepts that physics tackles. Color, taste, smell etc are state to be upholdary sensations, comprise or derived from the primary ones.The copy principle says that the primary sensations, though not bring throughing complete information from the visible object which is more poignantly described as the object in itself nevertheless is a faithful copy of it. This is why primary sensations are distinct and forceful presences in our mind. Secondary sensations are in turn copies of the orig inal copy, and collectable to this derivative temperament they lose edge to us. We will examine the copy principle of Hume in a moment.For the time being we accept it as such and moot the consequences. For Humes purposes, it has allowed him to refer to objects and their motions with confidence, and not to be held back by the validity of these concepts. For without the principle we dont know as yet that objects are objects, and motion is motion, and we would welcome had to deal with a loony bin of sense experience, and nothing meaningful to refer to it once morest (1993, p. 12).So now, with the copy principle of Hume as foundation, we bear on to talk about objects in motion. Next, we travel along interdependence between objects, carried out in space and time. We know that motion in one object is cause to motion in another.A billiard ball in motion strikes another, and after impact the second acquires a velocity too, and the faculty of our spirit tells us, without the least (prenominal) inkling of doubt, that the impact imparted by the first ball is the cause of the second ball gaining motion. This understanding is so refined that we can, with a little help from Newtons mechanics, predict the exact trajectory of the second ball by analyzing the trajectory of the first. We know it, scarce how do we know it? This is the crucial question for Hume. For if we do not have the answer we are left with skepticism.After impact with the first ball the second could have taken any one of an infinite number of trajectories. unless it takes only one, and indeed we involve it to take only that one. A physicist may come along and try to convince us that it could not have taken any other trajectory because the laws of motion stipulates that, with the initial conditions given, the path it takes is the only possible one. just now this is not an answer to the percipient of the billiard ball, because he doesnt care what the laws of physics are. If nature had followed another numeral law then another outcome would have been simply as valid.The observer could then have framed his conundrum differently Of the infinite possible mathematical laws why just that one? there is nothing in the inner system of logic of the situation that dictates that the first ball should make water exactly the prescribed trajectory in the second. Hume s supporter this about the essayal set-up, that we may try an experiment ten times, and may arrive at the exact aforementioned(prenominal) result ten times. But this does not prove that the specific outcome is inevitable. Not even if we confirmed the outcome a million times, because we would comfort only have a statistical probability and not a proof.Humes conclusion is that on that point is no rational link between cause and effect. Yet we expect effect to follow cause, like a shot and irrevocably. If this is so then, explains Hume, it is a feeling transmitted to us by custom. What exactly he means by custom is l eft vague. He could not have meant anything other than observing over and over again, even though this fails to take into account new experience.He himself supplies a famous counterexample in the Enquiry. nearly one who has experienced all the shades of blue, except for a tiny strip of the spectrum, is expected to fib a gap when looking at the full spectrum of blue. But the fact is that he does not observe a gap at all, and recognizes at once the full spectrum of blue, even though he is experiencing a particular shade on blue for the first time. The recognition was instantaneous, and the eye did require accustoming beforehand. This readily disposes the possibleness of custom. Hume, however, continues to insist that our convictions regarding cause and effect can have no other source than custom.That the proof to custom is a vague one is make clear when he comes to consider plain will. The rattling act of awareness, he says, testifies to the existence of free will. But coming t o reflect on how it is possible that we are able to willingly set our limbs into motion, and to course and external object thereby, it appears nothing less than miraculous. The mystery in nothing less than how one immaterial body imparts momentum to anotherFor first Is there any principle in all nature more mysterious than the union of soul with body by which a supposed spiritual substance acquires such an influence over a material one, that the or so refined thought is able to actuate the grossest depend? (Hume, 1993, p. 43)The upshot is that we cannot explain free will, just as sure as shooting as we cannot explain cause and effect. Custom was hesitantly introduced to explain cause and effect, and the same comes to the deliverance of free will. As constant observers of nature we come to expect an effect to always follow a cause, and the same analysis ought to be applied to the orbit of human will. In all times and in all places humans have shown a application in their day to day affairs, which points to a constancy in human nature. The speculation concerning the scope of free will is overdone by the philosophers, maintains Hume.The exercise of free will, when looked at through the vista of human history, does not display divergence as much as it displays constancy. Hume broaches on the distinction between freedom and necessity to make this point clear. Inanimate objects convey to us most clearly the quality of freedom. We may describe an inanimate object as indifferent to the rest of the material universe, and in that sense free. But this freedom also entails necessity. The object is subject to the necessary laws of causation, and indeed is bound entirely by them. This is the relationship that splices cause and effect to inanimate objects, and is a relationship that is composed of two freedom and necessity.Hume transposes the same analysis to the relationship between human beings and free will. The will is indeed free, but being so implies that it co nforms to human nature. He proposes the following definitionBy liberty, then, we can only mean a power of acting or not acting, correspond to the determinations of the will this is, if we choose to quell at rest, we may if we choose to move, we also may. (1993, p. 63)The notion of free will advanced here bears a crucial difference to the popular one, and begs to be spelt out. What Hume describes as free will is not a choice between course A and B. Rather the choice is between A and not A, the latter implying stagnation, not an alternative course. This is the entire extent of our free will. We choose either to move forrard, or else to stand still. This is what Hume would describe as freedom to act. Free will, however, is in complete accordance with human nature, and hence follows the laws of necessity, just as everything else in contingent reality. Free will urges us to act freely. With freedom to act we may respond to this urge, or we may desist.In the final analysis our underst anding of free will hinges on custom, in the same way as does our understanding of cause and effect. The ancient is guide to the future in the probabilistic sense. Beyond probabilities we have no understanding of either, contends Hume. In order to enforce this skepticism he proceeds to dismantle the Cartesian theories that pretended to explain mind and matter interaction, especially the theory of occasionalism advanced by Father Nicholas Malebranche.In this theory God is made both motivator and executor of every act or incident that seems to be cause, while the circumstances which we call a cause are only occasions for God to act in such a manner. Hume complained that this not only made God a slave to his own creation, but it also eradicated free will, making everything full of God (1993, p. 47). By disposing summarily the Cartesian explanations of cause and effect Hume makes his skepticism complete.Kant overcomes this skepticism by revising the premise of Hume. The correction is m ade most forcefully in the opening to the CritiqueAlthough all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it arises entirely from experience. For it is quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound of that which we receive through impressions and that which our own faculty of knowing (incited by impressions) supplies from itself (1999, p. 1)To be fair to Hume, he does consider this possibility, and ponders whether there is a blueprint in the mind where all causes and all effects can be referred back. (1993, p. 44). But he dismisses this idea when he realizes that a static blueprint can never account for the dynamic reality. However, the faculty that Kant is suggesting is not static, rather dynamic and creative, and here lies the crucial difference. In the technological terms of Kant it is the synthetic a priori faculty of the mind. This is distinguished from the analytic a priori faculty, such as logic. The rules of logic are extant in the mind (a pri ori), but form a self-consistent system (analytical), and therefore do not depend on sense experience.On the first instance it seems impossible that the mind can have a faculty that is synthetic a priori, where synthetic implies that it is creative. It entails that order is created out of the chaos of sense experience, and order that was not there before. But Kant also provides proof that the mind is capable of synthesis. numeric propositions are synthetic a priori, he contended. The proposition 3 + 5 = 8 may speech sound like self-consistent logic, but it is not really so. 8 is a completely new concept, and is not contained in either 3, 5 or +. If we know that 3 + 5 = 8, it is due to a synthetic a priori faculty in the mind.As Kant relates in the Prolegomena, when he realized that mathematical propositions are indeed synthetic a priori, it led him to ponder on what other such concepts the mind uses to facilitate understanding, and it appeared to him, in due course, that cause and effect was a concept of understanding that derives from the same faculty. He does not at all concern himself with material reality as a thing in itself, that which the materialist philosophers were after in order to provide a foundation to Newtonian science. Like Hume he maintains end-to-end that an absolute material reality is beyond knowledge, and to speculate on its existence was futile.We only need to consider what we perceive and what we do. He also shows that Hume falters at exactly those points where he cannot dismiss material existence in itself. The copy principle is slavish to a material object in itself. The object does not deliver copies to our mind rather the mind provides the concepts of space in which we are able to conjure up material objects from sensory data. Both space and time are pure concepts of the mind, contends Kant, and like cause and effect are the tools by which we come to understand contingent reality (Prolegomena, 2005, p. 26).As soon as it is made out that we are the responsible architects of our own reality, and are not passive bystanders to an absolute material reality beyond our control, we suddenly discover ourselves as clean beings. Therefore the subsequent direction of Kants philosophy, after the metaphysics of understanding has been established, is towards a metaphysics of morals.And so emerges the crucial distinction that Kant makes between functional and transcendental freedom. To say that we have practical freedom implies we are able to understand the world, and by doing so we direct the will accordingly. We will do so of course for practical purposes survival, utility, convenience, happiness etc. this would seem to cover the entire orbit of freedom. But Kant went on to demonstrate, in his Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), that such freedom is not actually freedom at all, and indeed is a binding. Thus far Kant is in concord with Hume.Now, the metaphysics of understanding, as spelt out in the Critique, is not the entire picture. The synthetic a priori faculty of the mind fashions understanding out of sensory experience. But such understanding does not lead to accuracy. As pure concepts of understanding space and time are both necessarily infinite. But because they emanate from the finite mind they are also finite. So in their very make-up space and time lead to contradictions. The same end must necessarily project anything that takes place within space and time. So that matter is both infinitely divisible and also made up of concrete building blocks.As another example, we have free will, but at the same time everything is caused, so we dont have free will. Such examples are put forward by Kant as pairs of antinomies. According to our understanding both consequences are valid, and yet they mutually contradict apiece other. All practical reasoning necessarily leads to pairs of antinomies.This must be so, because we reason by means of subject and predicate, where the subject is t he cause of the predicate. But this subject is in turn predicate to another subject, and so on in an infinite chain of causation. If there was an ultimate subject at the beginning of this chain, we could have claimed to have discovered the final cause, and thereby have at hand a pronouncement of truth. But in contingent reality there is no such final cause. So whenever we try to make pronouncements of truth we must face contradiction.We cannot say that practical reason is false for this reason. Life is govern by contingencies, and practical reason is to explain the contingent, or to facilitate such understanding. Absolute truth lies beyond all contingencies, and this is ruled by pure reason, explains Kant. It is not within the grasp of the human mind, yet it is the underpinning of the mind, and is the source of all nescient faculties.The same analysis applies to practical freedom, which is but the corollary to practical reason. With practical freedom we choose our course according to practical reason, i.e. we are motivated by self-serving motives happiness, honor, respectability, and so on. But in doing so we bind ourselves to those endless chains of contingencies, so that we are not really free. We chase material acquisition in order to be happy, and yet it always eludes us. The definition of freedom is to escape all contingencies, and yet by the application of practical reason we are mired more and more into contingent reality. Therefore we are not free.This is indeed a contradiction, one which Hume does not pay heed to. The very act of consciousness tells us that we are free, that out will is free. If practical reason does not embody this freedom, then surely pure reason must do so. By the same token, we are in possession of a transcendental freedom, which is a path that overcomes all contingencies, and is dictated by pure reason. Kant describes this path as the moral one. We recognize and follow this path from a sense of duty.To clarify what it is, duty is done for its own sake. There is no material motive whatsoever attached to it. Not for any particular good, it is done for the oecumenic good. It is a categorical imperative, meaning that the very make-up of our being, or pure reason, dictates that we follow it. As an aid to identifying ones duty Kant devised the following wording for the categorical imperative I ought never to act except in such a way that I could also will that my maxim should become a universal law (Moral constabulary, 2005, p. 74).Kant is described as overcoming Humes skepticism. But it is questionable whether the latter is a skeptic at all. According to a contemporary, Humes philosophical paradoxes are delivered with a confidence that belies skepticism Never has there been a Pyrrhonian more dogmatic (qtd. in Mossner, 1936, p. 129). A more recent review of Hume is carried out by the German Neo-Kantian philosopher Ernst Cassirer, who opines, Humes doctrine is not to be understood as an end, but as a new begi nning (1951, p. 59).The nature of this new beginning is well articulated by Hume himself. Indulge your passion for science, nature tells us, according to Hume, but let your science be human, and such as may have a direct reference to action and society (Hume, 1993, p. 3). If we listen carefully, the moral check that Hume is sounding is hardly different from that of the categorical imperative of Kant. Not for the persons sake, but for mans sake. Not for the particular good but for the universal good. This is the essence of Humes projected science of man, as it is also the heart of Kants metaphysics of morals.ReferencesCassirer, E. (1951). The Philosophy of the Enlightenment. Trans. Fritz C. A. Koelln and James P. Pettegrove. Boston Beacon Press.Hume, D. (1993). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. E. Steinberg (Ed.) Boston Hackett Publishing.Kant, I. (1999). Critique of Pure Reason. W. S. Pluhar (Trans.), E. Watkins (Ed.) Boston Hackett Publishing.Kant, I. (2005). Kants Prole gomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Whitefish, MT Kessinger Publishing.Kant, I. (2005). The Moral Law Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Translated by H. J. Paton. New York Routledge.Mossner, E. C. (1936). Bishop Butler and the Age of Reason A Study in the account statement Of Thought. New York Macmillan.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.